What
do we mean when we speak of sex work? Sex work is essentially any
form of labor in which persons receive money in return for using
their bodies in some way to titillate or arouse their customers.
Broadly, then, sex workers include pornographic models, phone sex
operators, high-priced escorts, street hookers, and even sexual
surrogates. Some sex workers are self-employed, and some work for
bosses (sometimes called madams or pimps) or companies. Sex workers
include people of all genders, races, classes, and nationalities,
although people who start out with more marginalized identities are
likely to find themselves operating under more stringent working
conditions.
Sex
work is not monolithic. Within every country, every city, and every
branch of the profession, there is a diverse range of experiences.
Nevertheless, sex work is often discussed as if it were one
single issue, a “topic” that can be defended or opposed. In this
essay, since I am focused on analyzing these modern feminist
responses to sex work (I will only be considering responses since
second-wave feminism), I will be omitting discussion of many of the
(especially gendered and raced) complexities of sex-worker
experience; however, it is important to keep in mind this present
absence.
Also, a note on
terminology: “sex work” is in itself a contested term. It has
not exactly replaced “prostitution,” since it encompasses
more forms of labor than “prostitution” (usually used to imply
streetwalking) does. However, many contemporary sex workers prefer
to refer to themselves as such rather than using the term
“prostitution” because “sex work” puts the emphasis on labor
rights rather than on gendered exploitation:
The term 'sex
worker' was coined by sex workers themselves to redefine commercial
sex, not as the social or psychological characteristic of a class of
women, but as an income-generating activity or form of employment for
women and men (Leigh, 1997). Similarly, use of the term 'sex
industry', was aimed at inclusion of exotic dancers, masseurs,
telephone sex operators, receptionists (maids) and a whole host of
people (including men) who sell sex (Delacoste and Alexander, 1987).
Both terms have gained increasing credence since the 1970s, better
acknowledging the active, wilful, moral, reflexive and insightful
agency of sex workers (Chapkis, 1997) and recognizing that the
prostitute is socially situated in a culture that includes a range of
other actors. 1
Many
anti-prostitution feminists despise the terminology change because
they believe it sugarcoats the harshly exploitative reality of the
career. 2
Some contemporary sex workers (as well as many other sex radicals)
are also reclaiming the words “whore” and “slut,” in order to
question the presupposition that sexual promiscuity is inherently
shameful. In this paper, I make use of all of the following terms:
“prostitution/prostitute,” “sex work/sex worker,” and
“whoring/whore.”
Theorizing Sex
Work:
Feminist/Sex-Worker
Responses (yes, it is possible to be either and both)
At
the risk of oversimplifying the issues, I find it useful to classify
the feminist responses to sex work into two categories:
anti-prostitution feminist and sex radical feminist/whore
revolutionary.3
This classification system is helpful for identifying some of the
common trends in the responses and for examining the tensions between
these trends. A note of caution, however: such a classification
system, if taken too literally, overdetermines the boundaries between
these groups and conceals the fact that some voices in these
movements, but not others, are heard because they are privileged by
media and history. Also, it is necessary to keep in mind the
specific historical contexts in which these theories arose and the
ways in which they were shaped by the experiences and identities of
their spokespeople. 4
Anti-Prostitution
Feminists
Prominent
second-wave feminists (many of whom were white and middle-class) such
as Andrea Dworkin5,
Catharine MacKinnon, and Kathleen Barry theorize prostitution (and
pornography, and sadomasochism, and butch/femme) as an example of
patriarchal power. They point to prostitution as an
institutionalization of men’s at-will access (sexual and otherwise)
to women. They reject a labor analysis of prostitution (including
the use of the term “sex work”) because they argue that it
obscures the inherently oppressive nature of prostitution. They base
the claim that prostitution is inherently oppressive on the idea that
it is always and necessarily involuntary, due to the ubiquity of
patriarchy, and on the idea that selling sex is selling part of the
self. They view prostitutes as victims unable to express agency,
constantly raped (all sex work is rape) and inherently rapable (by
nature of the profession, sex workers can never legitimately say no).
They often extend this victim analysis by seeing sex worker
theorists as having “false consciousness” if they challenge
anti-prostitution feminist theorizing of sex work. They tend to omit
a class or capitalist analysis of sex work, and they also omit an
analysis of pleasure and desire. Desire is presumed never to be
present on the part of sex workers, and clients’ desire is figured
as inherently predatory and pathological.6
The Feminist Sex
Wars and Sex Workers
In response to
utopian radical feminism, sex radical voices began to emerge, many of
which belonged to working-class women, including sex workers (two
queer working-class white women important to the sex radical movement
were Dorothy Allison and Amber Hollibaugh—Hollibaugh was also a sex
worker). Also, in the context of the more recent third-wave
feminism, more and more sex workers are speaking out and influencing
the direction of feminist organizing. Many sex workers’ writings
are now published. Carol Leigh’s book Unrepentant Whore: The
Collected Works of Scarlot Harlot7
is one example of this, as are the anthologies Sex Work: Writings
by Women in the Sex Industry,8
Working Sex: Sex Workers Write about a Changing Industry,9
and Whores and Other Feminists.10
Sex workers have also shared their perspective on tour through the
Sex Workers’ Art Show, a performance art tour performed entirely by
sex workers.11
Many sex workers have well-traveled online blogs
(http://renegadeevolution.blogspot.com/ is one) and some, like
Emi Koyama and Sarah Katherine Lewis, are popular campus speakers.
Sex workers working in legal portions of the industry are unionizing:
Julia Query’s film Live Nude Girls Unite12
documents the unionization of the Lusty Lady, a strip club in San
Francisco.
Sex
radical feminists and sex workers have responded to the
anti-prostitution positions by pointing out their failure to
adequately account for human desire and pleasure, and as such their
allegiance with reactionary and ascetic forces bent on labeling
unruly bodies and sexuality as dirty or pathological. (Priscilla
Alexander points out that the terms that are used by
anti-prostitution feminists—“degraded,” “dehumanized,” and
“debased,” for example, are the same that arise in the writings
of an “all-male commission that studied prostitution at the end of
the nineteenth century…[as well as] the patriarchs who wrote the
Torah.”13)
The recognition of these troubling alliances helps to build an
analysis of the ways in which sex-negativity actually bolsters
patriarchy by reinforcing the mind-body split, devaluing physical and
emotional (i.e., archetypically feminine) forms of knowledge,
reifying myths of women as sexually responsive (or frigid) and men as
sexually initiatory, reinforcing the virgin/whore dichotomy (and thus
permitting men to continue defining and regulating women’s
sexualities), increasing the invisibility of lesbian sexualities, and
essentializing gender, among other things. In addition, sex radical
feminists began to depart from the earlier feminist utopianism, both
by acknowledging that relations of power are often integral to human
desire, and by recognizing that under patriarchy, all choices are
necessarily constrained and imperfect, and thus no choices can be
immediately dismissed as “non-radical” (and by the same token, no
one is innocent of complicity with the power structure)14.
Since no actions are perfect but action is necessary to overthrow
patriarchy (“We can’t wait to have sex until after the
revolution!” 15),
formerly maligned activities suddenly came within the realm of the
potentially revolutionary. Based on this new view, the sex radical
feminists began to analyze how sex work could be subversive and
agentive, in order to counter the anti-prostitution feminist claim
that it (and pornography and sadomasochism and butch/femme) was
simply coerced reification of structures of patriarchal power.
In
contrast to the anti-prostitution feminists, sex radical feminists
argued that sex work was not inherently oppressive and was not any
more involuntary than any form of heterosexual sexuality under
patriarchy. Koyama writes:
[Prostitution is]
not any more [oppressive] than other lines of work in a global
capitalist system. If prostitutes were [sic] more vulnerable to
exploitation than other workers today, it is because we, like
offshore sweatshop workers and migrant farmworkers, lack the
institutional power to defend our rights as workers. To say
that prostitution is always or “inherently” oppressive would
absolve the wrongdoers of their responsibilities, and
therefore is ultimately reactionary. [emphasis present in the
original]16
Working-class
feminists add that sex work is not more exploitative than other forms
of labor under capitalism. In fact, under capitalism, all forms of
labor—especially working class labor—involve the alienated
selling of some part of the self. (For example, Emi Koyama points
out that the fact that migrant farmworkers and sweatshop workers are
exploited does not cause us to call for the abolition of agriculture
or the garment industry.17)
Sex
radicals also argue that sex workers subverted men’s enforced
access to women by making that access visible by taking payment for
it. Eva Pendleton writes (79), “[The act of making men pay]
reverses the terms under which men feel entitled to unlimited access
to women’s bodies. Sex workers place very clear limits on that
access, refiguring it on our own terms.”18
Sex radicals also emphasize sex work’s potential for women’s
ability to reclaim sexual agency, pleasure, desire, and control.
Adding to this
framework of choice-under-constraint, working-class sex workers have
corrected a middle-class sex radical position that emphasizes sex
work as a radical empowering choice for women. Working-class sex
workers argue that the shift from viewing sex workers as victims to
viewing them as having agency must not be so complete that it
obscures the very real constraints under which sex workers,
particularly working class sex workers, make the choice to enter or
remain in the industry, nor that it be allowed to obscure the
dangerous and terrible conditions under which many such women work.
For example, Koyama writes,
[B]y telling sex
workers that sex work is inherently empowering, [Carol Queen] was
making invisible the exploitation and abuse of workers by the
management, and making it easier for them to further the
exploitation. By labeling someone “anti-sex” for having
legitimate grievances against their working conditions, whether the
work involves sexual act [sic] or not, Queen’s pro-sex feminism
renders sex work as primarily sex as opposed to work—and thus her
argument is counteractive and anti-worker.19
Also,
sex workers point out that sex work has been insufficiently theorized
from the perspective of capitalism and class. It is these sex
workers who pushed for the shift toward the terminology of “sex
work” rather than prostitution, in order to emphasize that sex work
is indeed a form of labor that is taking place under the capitalist
system. This framework not only makes visible the effects of
capitalism on sex workers, it also emphasizes that it is possible to
address the abuse of sex workers through worker organization and
industry regulation rather than solely through abolition. By way of
one example of how this logic counters the arguments of
anti-prostitution prostitution abolitionists: whore revolutionaries
point out that sex workers should not be considered unrapable,
that consent should be part of the job and that sexual advances in
the absence of consent should be treated as sexual harassment just as
they would be in a middle-class work environment, rather than treated
as evidence of the inherent exploitative nature of sex work. Koyama
writes, “[A]nti-prostitution feminists share one thing in common
with rapists: that they do not understand ‘yes means yes, no means
no.’ While rapists argue in court that prostitutes can’t get
raped, anti-prostitution feminists argue that prostitutes can’t
avoid being raped—both arguments exonerate those directly
responsible for the act of raping.”20
Activist and
Policy Outcomes of the Theories
Based on these
theoretical differences, the two schools of thought recommend
different activist approaches to sex work.
Anti-prostitution
Feminists
Anti-prostitution
feminists suggest that since prostitution is an outgrowth and a
reinforcement of patriarchal oppression, it ought to be banned and
expunged. They have tended to approach this goal through an alliance
with state regulatory forces—laws and police. In some cases this
takes a supposedly pro-woman form by stipulating punishment of
clients rather than punishment of workers. (Even in places in which
clients are as criminalized as prostitutes, prostitutes (and
particularly working class women of color) tend to make up the bulk
of those targeted by police for violence, arrest, and jail time.21)
Grassroots activist work tends to focus on “rehabilitation”
programs for ex-sex-workers that combine needed resources with
enforced ideological compliance (for example, requiring a commitment
to leave the industry as a prerequisite for counseling or support
services). Emi Koyama describes the collusion between one such
program and law enforcement:
SAGE cooperates
with the law enforcement, which means that it gains its ‘clients’
by threatening prostitutes…that unless they go through its program
they will go to jail. Under this threat, it then demands women to
accept and internalize its anti-prostitution message….Talk about
women being kidnapped, brainwashed, and trapped in an abusive system
through enormous power differential!22
Sex Radical
Feminists and Whore Revolutionaries
Since
sex radical feminists recognize that prostitution can be an
empowering choice for women and potentially subversive toward the
patriarchy, and since they recognize that illegalization reinforces
the sex-negativity that in turn reinforces patriarchal oppression,
they call for decriminalization of prostitution and thus legal
protection for what can potentially become a site of subversion of
patriarchy.
Whore
revolutionaries point out that the typical feminist approach (trying
to eliminate sex work and liberate sex workers through state
legislation) is based on a series of faulty assumptions: that sex
work is inherently oppressive, that to abolish sex work is to
liberate sex workers to some life situation that is in fact less
oppressive, that this will on the whole help dismantle patriarchy
(and perhaps capitalism), that state legislation is effective in
abolishing prostitution, and that the harm such legislation does to
sex workers will be justified by the ultimate gains. None of these
assumptions is borne out. The criminalization of prostitution
disproportionately affects working-class sex workers and sex workers
of color, who are in the first place more likely to be working on the
streets, and who in the second place are more likely to be targeted
by police arrests23
(including deceitful tactics such as entrapment by plain-clothes
police24)
as well as violence (and since prostitution is illegal and
prostitutes’ voices are not often taken seriously by the court
system, sex workers’ attempts to get justice in response for police
brutality (or, for that matter, rape, assault, or murder at the hands
of clients) are almost never successful25).
Also, criminalization of prostitution provides a pretext for police
to pick up any “social undesirables,” even people who are not
clients or sex workers, or sex workers who are not working at the
moment of arrest.26
Also, under laws that prohibit “encouraging prostitution,”
police can arrest prostitutes for sharing safety information,
organizing to prevent abuse, and offering each other support27—and
as such, this legislation often makes prostitutes more vulnerable to
abusive pimps28
(who, unlike prostitutes, are rarely arrested by police when they are
reported). Under laws that prohibit “pimping, pandering, or
procurement” or “benefiting from prostitution,” prostitutes can
be arrested for voluntarily sharing resources with family and
friends, or can even have their own property taken away.29
Finally, laws designed to prevent the trafficking of sex workers or
their assets by exploitative pimps actually end up being used against
prostitutes themselves who try to send money across state borders or
themselves attempt to cross international borders, even sometimes
being deported when they are in fact immigrating as refugees from
trafficking.30
However,
not just any form of legalization will do. In some cases in which
prostitution is de facto (such as through tacit state acceptance that
sex work is being done under the auspices of “massage parlors” or
“escort services”) or de jure legal, conditions for sex workers
actually worsen. Sex workers may be forced to register with the
state, which increases their vulnerability to surveillance and police
targeting, while other prostitutes (who for one reason or another do
not “qualify” for state registration) are forced even further
underground.31
Thus, whore revolutionaries call for a particular form of
decriminalization (a term they use to distinguish their goals from
this less judicious “legalization”). By decriminalizing sex work
but using state power to regulate abuses against sex workers just as
state power is used to prevent exploitation in all sorts of
industries, decriminalization maximizes sex worker autonomy,
minimizes state surveillance, avoids forcing sex workers underground,
and maximizes the potential for group organizing to empower workers
and improve working conditions.32
Whore
revolutionaries call on feminists to relinquish their focus on
abolition and to stand by a whore-defined agenda for the appropriate
use of state power, as well as to stand with prostitutes to counter
other forms of state- and socially-sanctioned stigma, such as the
practice of returning juvenile runaways to abusive homes rather than
providing them with safe and anonymous shelter and support,33
and the scapegoating of sex workers as victims of abuse,34
drug-users, and vectors of sexually transmitted diseases.35
Feminist Classism
Omission
In
general, sex work is insufficiently taken into account by both gender
theorists and labor theorists. It could be argued that a small
percentage of the population is engaged in the sex industry and thus
the omission is arbitrary and justified in the same way as the
omission of studies of other industries. However, I would argue that
it is clear from popular culture and daily language that the
prostitute is an important cultural archetype against which “pure
people” constantly define themselves, and which defines the
boundaries of nation and citizenship both de facto and de jure.36
As such it is extremely crucial that sex work be taken into account
in any analysis of gender and labor. It is clear to me that, while
this omission may also be upholding racial and gender privilege, this
omission is at least partly a classist omission, an omission made
possible by the fact that so many theorists are middle-class and are
insulated from the realm in which sex work seems like a viable or
necessary option.
Not
only do theorists take sex work into account insufficiently, when
they do, they treat it as monolithic, failing to take into account
the diversity of sex workers’ genders, class status, individual
histories, job descriptions, races, ages, etc. (Carol Queen writes,
“[W]e learn next to nothing about those women for whom sex work is
an excellent occupational choice and nothing at all about sex
workers—isn’t it a bit ironic that men are present in the sex
industry in every capacity that women are, yet their lives, failing
to fit neatly into theory, are simply ignored?”37)
Once again, while this monolithicism also injures other parties, it
particularly injures working class sex workers by ignoring the
specificity of their experience—and thus of their theories and
needs—within the industry.
As
far as feminism in particular, the fact that many prominent feminist
theorists and activists are middle-class, coupled with the fact that
working-class feminists’ voices are often marginalized and
dismissed, makes it possible for the most common form of feminist
classism: the omission of a class analysis. Both anti-prostitution
and sex radical feminists are guilty of this. Anti-prostitution
feminists, who were mostly women who were not experiencing class
constraint, thus did not have as much need to theorize the
possibility for agency under constraint, because although they were
experiencing the constraint of patriarchy, their class (and usually
race) privilege insulated them from experiences of extreme
constraint. The utopian ideas of anti-prostitution feminism are also
comprehensible in this light: it is much easier to rely on delayed
gratification when class privilege affords you a high degree of daily
instant gratification.
For
their part, some sex radical feminists found it easy to theorize sex
work as an empowering, anti-patriarchal choice for women while at the
same time not understanding the extremity of the (often class-based)
constraint under which working-class sex workers were often making
that choice, or the violent and often fatal consequences of that
choice.
Devaluation,
Disrespect, and Paternalism
In addition to
their omission of a class analysis of sex work, feminists,
particularly anti-prostitution feminists, act in actively devaluing
and paternalistic ways towards especially working-class sex workers.
Anti-prostitution
feminists tend to see sex workers as complete victims who have no
possibility of agency because their choices are made under
constraint. This is a strange stance to take given that one of the
main tenets of radical feminism is that all women operate under
patriarchal constraint until the revolution. However, some actions
are considered to be exempt from that impurity (reciprocal sex,
androgyny, for example). Meanwhile, acts that disproportionately
involve working class women (not only sex work but also butch/femme
lifestyles) are considered more tainted by patriarchy, and thus
necessarily coerced (sex workers’ claims to agency can be easily
dismissed by attributing “false consciousness”). This idea of
complete victimhood is revealed through the idea of the always and
already raped whore (all sex work is rape), which eerily parallels
the patriarchal legalistic construction that whores can never refuse
(no sexual contact with a whore is rape). Both ideas reveal the idea
of the impossibility of consent due to complete victimhood. This is
not only classist in theory (insofar as middle-class women are
disproportionately unaffected by a life situation in which consent is
analyzed as impossible, despite all women existing under patriarchy),
but also classist in outcome (insofar as the idea of the
unrapable/constantly raped whore makes it impossible to think about
how to regulate or organize within the sex industry so that whores
have more control over the sexual boundaries they set on the job,
which would significantly lower physical and emotional danger). In
addition, the idea that whores cannot possibly take agency implies
that they require advocates and caretakers—conveniently,
middle-class feminists are waiting in the wings (voila!) to take on
this paternalistic task.
Just as sex workers
cannot possibly have agency, they also cannot have their own
analysis. Once again, anti-prostitution feminists justify this claim
by appealing to the notion of “false consciousness,” but this
thinly veils the class prejudice that makes many middle class people
unwilling or unable to take working-class people seriously as
intellectuals.38
(Amber Hollibaugh writes, “Why did it take so long for the women’s
movement to genuinely consider the needs of whores, of women in the
sex trades? And why did it take so long for the movement to produce
writings by those women? Maybe because it’s hard to listen to—I
mean really pay attention to—a woman who, without other options,
could easily be cleaing your toilet?”39)
Emi Koyama tells how she was told by Sarah Lawrence College, on
three days’ notice, that her speaking engagement was canceled
because the president of the college labeled her planed speech (about
sex worker feminism) “inappropriate and uneducational.”40
This attitude continues to be expressed in the current era—I
recently saw a posting for a “Prostitution Conference” in which
“professionals” working with prostitutes are planning to
convene—prostitutes themselves are, of course, not considered
professionals. (Under the heading “Who Should Attend,” the
website says, “This conference is open to researchers,
practitioners, and workers in the social service, criminal justice,
and health care fields.”) 41
The
conversation about whether or not sex work should be considered labor
is inherently classist. By any definition, any service performed
(even if not for money, such as housework) is labor. The reluctance
to consider sex work labor reflects classist standards for what labor
is. For example, to say that sex work is not labor because it
involves alienation (which is essentially the argument under the idea
that sex work is not labor because it is inherently exploitative
since it involves selling of the self) is approximately the same as
saying that no working-class labor is labor. Most working-class
labor involves high degrees of alienation on top of high degrees of
selling the self—the physical self in dangerous factory jobs, the
emotional self in pink-collar jobs (“Good morning, Dr. Jones, how
are you today?”), the sexual self in sex work. Also, to say that
sex work is inherently exploitative and not labor because it is not
regulated the way middle-class work sites are is also classist.42
Saying that
working-class labor is not labor is classist for several reasons.
First of all, as can be seen in the feminist desire to recognize
women’s unpaid housework and caretaking as labor, to entitle
something “labor” suggests social value. Secondly, the desire
not to consider sex work labor partially stems from the idea that if
it is legitimately viewed as labor, regulation will take the place of
abolition and the reality that sex work is inherently oppressive will
be obscured. This is classist because it takes a paternalistic
attitude towards sex workers by ignoring their requests for a very
specific type of support (recognizing sex work as labor,
decriminalizing it, supporting worker organizing) and by trying to
eliminate sex work as even a possible choice, as if
working-class women could not decide for themselves whether the costs
outweighed the benefits. (Abolition efforts disproportionately
affect the jobs of working-class sex workers.) A more respectful
ally position would recognize that while working-class sex workers
may not be making a “free choice,” they deserve support in the
choices they are making (and obviously will continue making despite
illegality), and they deserve both the option to get out of the
industry and safe working conditions for women within it.
Thirdly,
the refusal to consider sex work as labor makes it very difficult to
think about sex workers as anything more than victims—indeed very
hard to think about collective organizing such as unionizing—and
leaves middle class white feminists the only potential “caretakers”
for streetwalkers. As such, this refusal stands in the way of
decriminalization, unionization, and the development of worker
consciousness and empowerment. Empirically, this is the same as
standing in the way of saving women’s lives and selves. Thus, this
investment in terminology reflects a highly classist devaluation of
working class (and possibly “sexually deviant”) lives. Fourthly,
the refusal to consider sex work labor reinforces very conservative
notions of monogamy, policed sex, non-promiscuity, sex in the private
sphere, notions of sex as the province of the feminine (which
coincides with the idea that emotional and caretaking labor are not
labor because they take place in the private sphere), and bodies in
general in a way that reproduces an oppressive mind/body split that
is unhelpful for social healing and for gender equity as a whole.
Sex
workers also point out that middle-class anti-prostitution feminists’
elaborate theorizing seems to be a mask for their disgust for whores
(fear of being branded whores?). Anti-prostitution feminists seem to
have some inconsistency in their theory about agency as it pertains
to sex work: they both pity sex workers as victims (of patriarchy and
false consciousness) and accuse them of perpetuating patriarchy,
expressing disgust and dismay about their “choices,” as if their
jobs inherently devalue the women themselves as legible humans
deserving of respect and protection (read: radical feminists with
“good” politics).
Scapegoating
The
sex industry is punished by prostitution abolitionists for making
visible the ways in which, under patriarchy, sexuality is often
exchanged for goods and services, and may be split off from erotic
desire. This is a form of scapegoating. The reality is that a lot
of heterosexual sex in this culture happens under some kind of
constraint and in the absence of desire. Traditional marriage,
arguably, reinforces this more than sex work, because in marriage the
exchange of goods (both material and moral—how do you keep wife
status and avoid whore status? by not reporting marital rape) is
invisible. Also, as far as the injury caused by alienating one’s
own labor, sex might be one of the easiest activities to alienate
from without further injury because, sadly, women in this culture are
likely to learn that skill well whether or not they work in the sex
industry.
Also, the sex industry is no more sexist than other industries. Koyama writes:
Also, the sex industry is no more sexist than other industries. Koyama writes:
Since we live in a
sexist society, every industry is guilty of incorporating sexist
elemtns [sic] to a degree. In the medical field for example, doctors
are disproportionately male while nurses female [sic] as a result of
the pervasive institutionalized sexism. Sex industry [sic] similarly
reflects the society’s sexist structures and attitudes. On the
other hand, it is one of the few fields where women make at least
as much as men if not more for the same work, and there is a lot
of female companionship and rapport among female sex workers.
Scapegoating the sex industry for its sexism trivializes the
far-reaching impact of the sexism in other fields.43
In
fact, sex work can be a site of subversive possibility, in which
women learn how to keep their sexuality separate from their desire so
that they do not internalize sexual abuse. (Carol Queen writes,
“[S]ex-positive whores have learned to sexually negotiate at the
intersection of our clients’ desires, our limits and boundaries,
and with regard to issues of safety and emotional well-being. Were
we to be acknowledged by orthodox feminists as the experts we are,
our voices could help push the feminist analysis of sex in positive,
productive directions.”44)
Learning how to completely alienate sexual service can be a hugely
liberating thing in a world in which the vast majority of women have
to give sexual service without consent at some point in their lives.
(A commonly quoted statistic is that 1 in 4 college women is raped
during her college career.) Also, it is important to note that
archetypically, sex is split off from desire much more for men than
for women. Thus, a space in which women consciously split sex from
desire might be a way of demystifying sex for women and fighting
against the sexual double standard (men are players, women are sluts,
women are virgins, men are babies). Teri Goodson writes (250-251),
Proper women are
socialized to associate sex with intimacy and often have difficulty
negotiating their desires with men. Yet men are able to more easily
distinguish between love and sex. They hold an advantage because
they can enjoy erotic pleasure without the emotional restrictions so
many women wrestle with. Our culture disproportionately discourages
such behavior in women and will continue to do so until feminists
claim such privileges for themselves.45
Whore
revolutionaries argue that since sex work is no more inherently
oppressive than other forms of sexuality under patriarchy or other
forms of labor under capitalism, the attempt to abolish the sex
industry turns out to be a way of scapegoating the sex industry, sex
workers, and clients and punishing them for the massive destruction
borne out by the real culprits—patriarchy, capitalism, racism,
heterosexism, etc.—rather than attacking those systems at the core.
46
This is not only a form of classism (attacking a disproportionately
working class population (even though middle-class sex workers are
also being attacked, they are much less affected by abolitionist
attempts’ collusion with the state)) but also a missed opportunity
to transform culture in a way that is broadly liberating and
healing—and to recognize sex work and sex worker theory as a
potentially subversive site from which to do this revolutionary work.
47
Thus, abolishing
prostitution is not a logical way to resolve the reality of coerced
sex and alienated labor. What is at issue here—and this is an
issue for sex workers and their allies—is to think about how the
industry itself could be set up so that women can learn how to split
off healthily if that is what they wish to do. This is encouraged by
feminist awareness, which would be encouraged by decriminalization.48
The Middle-Class
Investment in Classist Analyses of Sex Work
If
there is so much classism in anti-prostitution feminist analyses, and
if the activist outcomes of anti-prostitution theory are so damaging
to sex workers, why do so many feminists still hang onto them despite
having been challenged by whore revolutionaries?
In
the first place, it is necessary to consider in what way middle-class
feminist classism is rooted in unwillingness to give up class
privilege. Middle-class people throughout the US (as well as some
working class people) are invested in the idea that the US is a
classless society, because it anesthetizes their own fear of downward
mobility49
and their guilt about class privilege. The myth of classlessness
(and its handmaidens, class segregation and the myth of meritocracy)
enables middle-class people not to “see” poverty, not to
acknowledge that people at different class levels have different
experiences and needs, and, most of all, not to share resources.
This blindness to the reality of class oppression in the US helps to
explain the inability to see and hear working-class women’s class
analyses of sex work, which in turn bolsters the process of
scapegoating. I think that the myth of classlessness takes on a
particular strength in feminist communities, however, since white
middle-class feminists have long been unwilling to recognize
differences within the community because of the threat it presented
to “women as a class” fighting against patriarchy. Also,
feminists, like all politicized oppressed people, are sometimes
liable to think that, as the oppressed, they could never be the
oppressor. Also, feminists, as self-consciously progressive people,
may try to avoid guilt about their own privilege by denying it. Such
feminists adopt a “hip downward mobility”50
and look askance at anyone who takes the resources of the system to
make a profit—because, not incidentally, they have the privilege to
not need to make one. This behavior passes for class solidarity but
actually stands in the way of a more honest recognition of the
damages of capitalism and of class privilege. The denial of class
privilege, the pretense of a classless society, the maintenance of
class privilege, all enable such feminists to refuse to recognize the
legitimacy of basing choices on access to resources. The result of
this is that working class women’s choice to enter the sex industry
is seen as more constrained and less agentive than other constrained
choices that are not based on class. Seeing class constraint as more
victimizing than other forms of constraint is yet another form of
classism. Insidiously, of course, this failure to acknowledge
classism allows feminists to hold onto an analysis of sex work that
allows them to maintain their access actually to the patriarchal
money structure by working in cooperation with forces (particularly
the state) that keep working class women from accessing economic
power.
In
the second place, I think the scapegoating phenomenon explains a lot.
Middle-class feminists are full of pain and rage about patriarchy
(and particularly sexual assault and compulsory heterosexuality), and
even about capitalism (the devaluation of traditional women’s
labor, the patrilineal transfer of resources, the mind-body split
required to traverse the etiquette of middle-class-ness, the class
division among women, self-deprivation that comes from the fear of
falling, the economic exploitation that middle-class feminists may
experience for the first time as they leave the safe haven of their
material connections with men). Middle-class women are also full of
fear. They are full of fear about losing what privilege they have,
especially in light of their gender-based marginalization. They are
full of fear about losing class privilege. Their class privilege is
already endangered by their challenge to patriarchy and thus to those
holding the majority of assets)—and recognizing classism, sharing
resources, and standing as allies with working class women (becoming
a class traitor) further endangers it. They are also full of fear of
losing what “well-genderedness” they still have despite their
challenge to patriarchy. Depending on the person, this
well-genderedness might involve being a wife, not a whore, or being
sexually “acceptable” (by radical feminist standards) rather than
“deviant” (practicing sadomasochism, doing sex work, liking or
posing for pornography, being butch/femme, being promiscuous, being
overtly sexual). Whores (literal sex workers or just women or queers
who due to their refusal to be regulated are labeled whores) are
still treated terribly, and becoming an ally to a whore is likely to
lead to being labeled a whore. (Circuitously, and arguing against
her own claim, Kelly Holsopple writes, “Supporting prostitution as
consensual sexual activity and labor will not protect these feminists
from being treated like prostitutes. Making sure that a class of
woman is available for men’s profit and pleasure will not protect
other classes of women from harassment, battery, rape, torture, and
murder. Because guess what? Men treat prostitutes like women.”51)
It is important to recognize that the fear of being labeled a
prostitute is justified. (Amber Hollibaugh writes, “The whore
stigma is not imaginary; it underscores the ‘good girl/bad girl’
dichotomy we all grow up with and pinpoints the punishment in store
for any woman who ‘slips’ from being madonna to being whore.”52)
Being labeled a whore is not just a momentary insult. Being a whore
makes you ineligible for state recognition (if you are not a whore,
you are a wife, and are thus eligible for patriarchal protection,
whether in the form of marriage (yes, I would argue that the whore
label is surreptitiously mobilized against queers seeking state
recognition of their relationships) or in the form of protection from
pathologization, surveillance, and criminalization). Being a whore
makes you dirty, inhuman, less-than-female. It is scary to risk
being a whore. But also, for non-whores, it is scary to think that
whores might be liberated—if it becomes clear that the oppression
of whores was never based on a rational justification, then non-whore
status is no longer a badge of pride, and access to humanization and
recognition are no longer the province of the well-gendered.
Whores
are scapegoated because provide an easy target for women’s rage and
fear. Whores are not protected by the state, and they are kept
sufficiently invisible that it is possible to conveniently ignore
them when they tell you that your political stance is killing them.
Also, because whores are easy to imagine as victims, it is easy to
conceal this attack in the clothing of “charity.” Thus,
middle-class feminists can vent their rage and see themselves as
moral all at the same time. This also neatly avoids the difficult
tasks of actually confronting the power structure (which just might
kill you if you look at it the wrong way) and of recognizing and
grieving for the depth and permanence of the damage caused by
patriarchy and capitalism. Much easier to believe that that damage
has a quick fix, that eliminating a situation in which choices are
made under dehumanizing constraint will magically erase all the other
circumstances in which choices are inevitably made under dehumanizing
constraint—even in middle-class lives. Also, easier to believe
that sex, particularly sex that recognizes the eroticism of power, is
dirty than to face up to our own “dangerous desires”53—desires
that, if acknowledged, could set us free, but which also force us to
face the degree to which trauma has permeated our deepest selves.
Also, easier to believe that if no one explicitly acknowledges that
heterosexual service is in exchange for resources, then no
heterosexual service is in exchange for resources (“No,
really, this is true love”/“If I don’t get paid for it, why
should she? By profiting from her oppression, isn’t she reifying
the system?”) The industry is targeted for making visible what is
already true, which is that emotional labor and sexual labor are
always and already being bought and sold.
White
Middle-Class Women Becoming Allies to Sex-Workers:
Healing Classism,
Healing Ourselves
The
whore label is attached to anyone who is “out of bounds,” not
only those who work in the sex industry54—and
disproportionately women of color, working class women, and
queers—such that sex workers and other people labeled “whores”
become the bearers of social defilement and impurity.55,56
Thus, the whore image is used to regulate people—women to be
monogamous, queers to be as asexual as possible. This image presents
an “other” against which “pure people” can define themselves.
This relieves people from dealing with the messy realities of
deviance, desire, and desperation in themselves and in their
communities, which relieves people of doing real healing around the
way in which the regulatory whore image hurts all of us.
One
really good reason for middle-class women to stand in solidarity with
working-class sex workers is that if we do not, those sex workers
will continue to die and be destroyed. However, solidarity is
sometimes only possible when we understand why it benefits us (this
is the interest convergence concept from critical race theory).
Every system of privilege and oppression hurts everyone, not just the
oppressed. It is true that the oppressed bear the brunt of the
system on their bodies. However, the damage is universal. For those
feminists who are privileged, privilege may mean the loss of
solidarity with sisters. It may mean guilt and subsequent
self-deprivation. It may mean fear of losing privilege, which may
lead to self-regulation and constraint. In the case of middle-class
women’s failure to be allies to working class sex workers, classism
(mind you, classism, not class) divides the effort to end sexism.
Classism (in the context of capitalism) also reifies a mind-body
split and distorts our experiences of desire. Fear of being labeled
whores (i.e. badly-gendered threats to the heteropatriarchy) leads to
sexual constraint, limited dissemination of sexual health
information, and insufficient sexual exploration and healing.
Thus,
it would actually benefit white middle-class women to stand in
solidarity with working class sex worker feminists. When we exit
denial about the extent of power of patriarchy and capitalism, we
begin to work through class guilt. This may relieve us of habits
that both hurt ourselves and squander resources: for example,
hoarding and self-deprivation. Also, when we learn from sex workers’
ability to theorize choice under constraint in a complex manner,
middle-class women can recognize a whole range of new subversive
options for taking agency within our own circumstances of constraint.
In particular, we can reclaim parts of desire that we shut ourselves
away from out of our fear of being labeled whores. As we reclaim
desire and sexuality, we fight sexism and promote sexual healing for
people of all genders and sexual orientations. Koyama writes,
to be a slut in
this u.s. of fucking a.
that thinks that
marriage is the solution to poverty
that punishes
homeless people for sitting on benches
and excludes trans
people to protect “women”
means that we must
refuse to allow the rhetoric
of safety to
pervert and circumvent
our commitment to
justice
so, let us be
sluts, political or otherwise
let us form the
posse of sluts everywhere
because everyone is
safe when sluts are safe
because everyone is
safe when sluts are safe.”57
Also,
fighting for the human rights of whores makes sex work become a more
viable option for all of us—and certainly, at the very least, we
can learn to listen to sex workers and open ourselves to all the
knowledge that their unique vantage point has taught them about
gender, labor, and desire. Teri Goodson writes,
Many women would
like to know how to enhance their sex lives and relationships. They
could benefit from associating with seasoned sex professionals, many
of whom would gladly share their insights and expertise. These
teachers are known as sacred prostitutes, mythologists, sex
educators, or sensual masseuses. Their knowledge and expertise in
the field of the erotic arts is sorely needed and should be highly
valued.58
Ultimately,
then, classist understandings of sex work reflect denial of class
privilege and the misdirection of capitalism- and
heteropatriarchy-related rage onto sex workers. This not only
desperately hurts sex workers themselves, but in fact perpetuates the
very structures that are wounding middle-class feminists, which takes
us further from healing. Thus I recommend that middle-class
feminists listen, really listen, to sex workers, learn from them,
become their allies. If we do this, all of us will be one step
closer to wholeness.
1
Wendy Rickard, “Been There, Seen It, Done It, I've Got the
T-Shirt: British Sex Workers Reflect on Jobs,
Hopes, the Future and Retirement,” Feminist
Review (No. 67, Spring 2001, 111-132), 111.
2
“Andrea Dworkin and others denied that prostitution could be
accepted as a free choice for any woman and suggested that seeing
prostitution as work misleads feminists into legitimizing systems of
abuse and exploitation (Dworkin, 1987).” Ibid, 112.
3
Borrowed from the title of Emi Koyama’s pamphlet, Instigations
from the Whore Revolution: A Third-Wave Feminist Response to the
Sex-Work “Controversy” (Second Edition, Dec. 2002—available
for download at http://www.confluere.com/store/zine-emi.html).
4
Chela Sandoval (Methodology of the Oppressed, Minneapolis:
Minnesota University Press, 2000) and Donna Haraway (“A Manifesto
for Cyborgs,” Socialist Review No.80 (March-April 1985),
580-617) write about the risks inherent in creating a watertight
taxonomic or genealogic history of thought.
5
For example, Andrea Dworkin, Intercourse, New York: Free
Press, 1987.
6
Carol Queen writes (131), “It is as though sex, especially male
sex, is a bubbling cauldron of trouble, and if we don’t keep a lid
on it, awful things will result” (“Sex Radical Politics,
Sex-Positive Feminist Thought, and Whore Stigma,” in Jill Nagle,
ed., Whores and Other Feminists (New York: Routledge, 1997),
125-138).
7
San Francisco: Last Gasp, 2004.
8
Frédérique Delacoste and Priscilla Alexander, eds., Pittsburgh:
Cleis Press, 1987.
9
Annie Oakley, ed., Emeryville, CA: Seal Press, 2007.
10
Nagle.
11
http://www.sexworkersartshow.com/home.html
12
San Francisco: First Run Features, 2000.
13
“Feminism, Sex Workers, and Human Rights,” 83, in Nagle, 83-97.
14
“We know that the time for utopian feminist revolution is over.
The forms of opposition we create are necessarily impure and draw
from the very systems of oppression we wish to overthrow” (ibid,
81).
15
Gayle Rubin talks about the utopian feminist image of “perfect sex
after the revolution” (in Amber Hollibaugh, My Dangerous
Desires(Durham: Duke University Press, 2000), 120).
16
Koyama, 3.
17
Ibid, 2.
18
“Love for Sale: Queering Heterosexuality,” in Nagle, 73-82.
19
Koyama, 31.
20
Ibid, 27.
21
Alexander in Nagle, 86.
22
Koyama, 28.
23
Priscilla Alexander (197), “Prostitution: A Difficult Issue for
Feminists,” in Delacoste and Alexander, eds. 184-214.
24
Alexander in Nagle, 85.
25
For example (283), see Rachel West, “U.S. PROStitutes Collective,”
in Delacoste and Alexander, eds., 279-289.
26
Alexander in Nagle, 85.
27
Ibid, 93.
28
Alexander in Delacoste, 209.
29
Ibid.
30
Alexander in Nagle, 91.
31
Alexander in Delacoste, 191.
32
For an example of these specific decriminalization demands, see
International Committee for Prostitutes’ Rights, “International
Committee for Prostitutes’ Rights World Charter and World Whores’
Congress Statements,” in Delacoste and Alexander, eds., 305-321.
33
Alexander in Delacoste, 205.
34
Koyama, 3.
35
Alexander in Nagle, 88-89.
36
See Gail Pheterson, “The Social Consequences of Unchastity, “ in
Delacoste and Alexander, 215-230.
37
Queen, 128.
38
See Joanna Kadi, “Stupidity Deconstructed,” in Thinking
Class, Sketches from a Cultural Worker. Boston: South End P,
1996.
39
Hollibaugh, 181.
40
Koyama, 33.
41
http://www.prostitutionconference.com/
42
Koyama, 29.
43
Ibid, 4.
44
Queen, 134-135.
45
“A Prostitute Joins NOW”, 248-251, 250-1.
46
Koyama, 32.
47
Pendleton analyzes how sex work can be a site from which to “queer
heterosexuality” through the explicit performance of it (drag)
that is made possible by getting paid.
48
Queen discusses the ways in which organizing encourages
sex-positivity among sex workers, which in turn helps protect sex
workers psychologically.
49
For an analysis of this, see Barbara Ehrenreich, Fear of Falling:
The Inner Life of the Middle Class. New York: Pantheon, 1989.
50
Bonnie J. Morris, “Class Beyond Classroom”, 391-396, in Out
of the Class Closet: Lesbians Speak, Julia Penelope, ed.,
Freedom, CA: The Crossing Press, 1994.
51
From “Pimps, Tricks, and Feminists” in WSQ, Spring/Summer
1999, p50.
52
Hollibaugh, 183.
53
Borrowed from Hollibaugh’s title.
54
“[I]t’s important to keep in mind that not only prostitutes are
labeled whores.” Hollibaugh, 184.
55
See Pheterson.
56
Also, see Joan Nestle’s account (“Lesbians and Prostitutes: A
Historical Sisterhood,” in ibid, 231-247) of how similar laws and
social stigmas have been applied historically to both lesbians and
prostitutes (who can, of course, be one and the same).
57
Koyama, 43—from the poem “Refusing to be Safe.”
58
251.
No comments:
Post a Comment